Fue escrito por mi en 1996.




RETHINKING THE 1995 NUCLEAR TESTS CASE.

JUDICIAL SUPPORT FOR EMERGING PRINCIPLES OF INTERNATIONAL ENVIRONMENTAL LAW

Germán Vera Esquivel[1]

INTRODUCTION

The resumption of the French nuclear tests in the South Pacific in 1995 and de judgment of the International Court of Justice[2] (hereinafter called “the ICJ”) concerning those tests have generated great polemic in the international arena.[3]

To cover comprehensively all possible aspects of the Nuclear Tests case would exceed the scope of this article. Our intention is rather modest, to limit the coverage of this paper only to issues related to international environmental law. It is intended to focus specifically in the three dissenting opinions of the court, those of judges Koroma, Weeramantry and judge ad-hoc Palmer.

The dissenting judges found that the Court should have reopened the case of 1974[4] and therefore could have analyzed the merits of the petition which New Zealand filed in 1995.[5] To support their position, the judges indicated, among other arguments, that certain principles of international environmental law existed. These were namely inter alia, the precautionary, sustainable development and preventive principle. Judges Koroma, Weeramantry and Palmer did not only describe these principles of international environmental law, but stated that they should have been applied by the Court in order to halt the French nuclear tests near the Mururoa and the Fangataufa Atolls.

This article will explore the principles of international environmental discussed in the dissenting opinions, In our view, the analysis of these principles of international environmental law is important for two reasons. First, because it will help to establish that the principles of international environmental law have existence and validity in general international law. Secondly, it will help to determine the degree of international obligation attached to those principles according to the current state practice, that is, whether or not these principles are legally binding.

To develop these ideas this article is divided into five parts. In the first part, the two cases brought before the Court by New Zealand, 1973 and 1995, will be reviewed. In the following section the dissenting opinions will be briefly summarized. In part three, a brief appraisal of the tests will be made from the point of view of the international relations. In part four, the principles of international environmental law by the dissenting judges will be analyzed. Part 5 analyze the debate regarding the obligations arising from environmental principles and finally, some preliminary conclusions will be presented.



PART 1.

1.1.- THE 1974 NUCLEAR TEST

(NEW ZEALAND AND AUSTRALIA V. FRANCE) CASE.

The ninth of May 1973 New Zealand presented a case to the International Court of justice against France. In the application New Zealand asked the Court for a declaration in the following terms:

“That the conduct by the French Government of nuclear tests in the South Pacific Region that give rise to radio-active fall-out constitutes a violation of New Zealand’s rights under international law, and that these rights will be violated by any further such tests.”[6]

New Zealand specifically requested the cessation of any nuclear activity in the areas of two atolls located inside of French Polynesia: the Mururoa and the Fangatufa  Atolls.[7]

After the presentation of the case, the Court adopted the denominated provisional measures of protection. That is, according to the article 41(1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice, “(t)he Court shall have the power to indicate, if it considers that circumstances so require, any provisional measures which ought  to be taken to preserve the respective rights of either party”. [8] In essence, by ruling that such measures be adopted, the Court demonstrated a concern for the effects of the French actions. By allowing such measures before jurisdiction and admissibility were proven, the Court could be said at this stage to be adopting a precautionary approach.[9]

Unfortunately for environmental jurisprudence, but fortunately for the environment, the Court never had the opportunity to discuss the legal issues involved because France declared that it had no intention to continue its atmospheric nuclear tests.[10] On the twentieth December of 1974, the Court delivered its judgment in which it fundamentally considered that the case presented by New Zealand no longer had any purpose because of the French declaration and thus the judicial process was considered finished by all parties. Even at this stage, there was disappointment expressed that the Court did not avail itself of the opportunity to make some comments about environmental principles[11].

1.2 THE 1995 NUCLEAR TESTS CASE:

THE REQUEST FOR AN EXAMINATION OF THE SITUATION IN ACCORDANCE WITH PARAGRAPH 63 OF THE COURT’S JUDGEMENT OF 20 DECEMBER 1974 IN THE NUCLEAR TESTS (NEW ZEALAND V. FRANCE) CASE. 22 SEPTEMBER 1995.

 On the thirteenth of June 1995, France announced the resumption of its nuclear tests in the South Pacific, declaring its intention to carry out a series of eight nuclear tests commencing in September 1995[12]. On the twenty-first of August 1995 New Zealand filed an application against France in response to this declaration.

New Zealand based its application on an interpretation of paragraph 63 of the 1974 Judgment of the Court. New Zealand argued that this paragraph included a “right” to re-open the case of 1974 if the basis of the 1974 Judgment had been affected.

The operative part of paragraph 63 of the 1974 case reads as follows:

“Once the Court has found that a State has entered into a commitment concerning its future conduct it is not the Court’s function to contemplate that it will not comply with it. However, the Court observes that if the basis of this Judgment were to be affected, the Applicant could request an examination of the situation in accordance with the provisions of the Statute…”[13]

Accordingly, taking into account the interpretation of paragraph 63 of the 1974 Case, New Zealand asked the Court to make a declaration to the effect that the conduct of the proposed nuclear tests would constitute a violation of the rights of New Zealand under international law, as well as other states. It further request that the Court declare that is unlawful for France to conduct such nuclear tests before it has undertaken an Environmental Impact Assessment according to accepted international standards. Unless such an assessment establishes that the tests will not give rise, directly or indirectly, to radioactive contamination of the marine environment the rights under international law of New Zealand, as well as the rights of other states, will be violated.[14]

New Zealand also requested the Court to adopt the Provisional Measured of Protection, based on article 41(1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice. These were that France refrain from conducting any further nuclear tests as Mururoa and Fangataufa Atolls, undertake an environmental impact assessment of the proposed nuclear tests, and ensure that no action of any kind is taken which might aggravate or extend the dispute submitted to the Court or prejudice the rights of the other Party in respect of the carrying out of whatever decisions the Court may give in this case.[15]

France responded to New Zealand’s application by firstly declaring it did not accept the jurisdiction of the Court. Secondly, France argued that the reopening of the 1974 case was not possible due to the original application of New Zealand having been presented to avoid nuclear tests in the atmosphere, whereas now France intended to carry out nuclear tests underground. Moreover, during the judicial process, France made the declaration that irrespective of the judgment of the Court, they would proceed with the nuclear tests.

After the oral presentations of both countries the majority of the Court delivered its judgment the 22 of September 1995. The Court reached the conclusion that the 1974 judgment related only to atmospheric tests and that it therefore could not consider the legality of underground tests pursuant to paragraph 63 of the 1974 Judgment.[16]

The majority thus dismissed the New Zealand Application by twelve votes to three. In favor were: President Judge Bedjaoui, Vice President Schwebel and the judges: Oda, Guillaume, Shahabuddeen, Ranjeva, Herczegh, Shi, Fleischhauer, Vereshchetin, Ferrari Bravo and Higgins. The dissenting judges were: Weeramantry, Koroma and the judge ad-hoc Geoffrey Palmer.[17]

While the majority did not allow the re-opening of the case he Court did note “the development of international law in recent decades”[18] and stated that the Order was “without prejudice to the obligations of States to respect and protect the natural environment.”[19]

Further, the separate decision of Judge Shahabuddeen, notes that the “growing recognition of the need to protect the natural environment is striking.”[20] Such comments indicate that the Court does acknowledge the existence of environmental principles, but as they were not applied by the majority it is to the dissenting opinions which we now turn.

PART 2

THE DISSENTING OPINIONS OF THE 1995 CASE

Once again disappointment has been expressed by some commentators that the Court did not avail itself the opportunity to clarify principles of international environmental law.[21]  The dissenting judges also expressed such disappointment and the proceeded to use such principles themselves to come to a different conclusion to the majority of the Court being that the Court should have analyzed the merits of the case and consequently could have prevented the French nuclear tests. In general, there are two arguments presented by the judges to support this conclusion. One is a procedural argument – related to the distinction between atmospheric and underground tests – and the other derives from the development of international environmental law. It is the latter of these which is the focus of this paper.



2.1 Judge Weeramantry:

Judge Weeramantry highlights the fact that the Court has demonstrated a deep concern for the effect of the tests by discussing the adoption of interim measures.[22] Indeed it is salutary to note this in the context of this paper, as it reminds us that the Court is not without sympathy for the effects of nuclear testing and was at least prepared to take some precautionary action. However, such sympathy was not sufficient for the majority to reopen the case.

For the present purposes, the most important part of Weeramantry’s judgment is his argument that the Court is not without sympathy for the effects of nuclear testing and was at least prepared to take some precautionary action. However, such sympathy was not sufficient for the majority to reopen the case.

For the present purposes, the most important part of Weeramantry’s judgment is his argument that the Court could have come to the conclusion to stop the French nuclear tests on the basis of the principles of international environmental law.

Weeramantry clearly sets out six principles: the inter-temporal principle, the concept of intergenerational rights, the precautionary principle, environmental impact assessment (EIA), the illegality of introducing radio-active waste into the marine environment and the principle that damage must not be caused to other nations. For each principle he gives clear examples of international treaties, declarations and academic writings which support the principle. He expresses disappointment that the Court did not avail itself of the opportunity to enquire and make a contribution to the “seminal principles of the evolving corpus of international environmental law”.[23]

2.2 Judge Koroma:

Judge Koroma notes that this was the second New Zealand application refused by the Court. He analyzed in depth the arguments for and against re-opening the case, concluding that the majority applied the incorrect standard of proof and wrongly refused to consider the application.

Again, the most important aspect of justice Koroma’s opinion in his mention of the principles of international law pertaining the environment. In his judgment justice Koroma states that there is “probably a duty not to cause gross or serious damage which could reasonably be avoided together with a duty no to permit the escape of dangerous substances.”[24] He cites a growing number of treaties which indicates wide support for such principles.

In conclusion he finds that nuclear tests per se are not only prohibited, but would be illegal if they cause radioactive fallout. Further, that in his view, the evidence is such that a risk of fallout exists and therefore the Court should have halted the tests.

2.3 Judge Palmer:

Ad-hoc judge Sir Geoffrey Palmer, appointed by New Zealand, criticized France’s arguments as legalistic and unrealistic, allowing the Court to avoid substantive and controversial issues. He argued that there were two main reasons why the Court should have examined the 1974 judgment. The first argument being that pertinent facts have changed which have increased our knowledge about the risks of nuclear contamination. Secondly, international environmental law has developed had progressed rapidly from the point it was in 1974 “towards international legal maturity”.[25]

Palmer set out the development of international environmental law, concluding that “the obvious and overwhelming trend of these developments from Stockholm to Rio has been to establish a comprehensive set of norms to protect the global environment”. The principles of international environmental law relied upon by Palmer were the prohibition of introducing radioactive material into the marine environment, the precautionary approach, environmental impact assessment and the inter-temporal principle.

To have a clear view of the principles of international environmental law mentioned by the judges in their dissenting opinions, a chart has been prepared.

TABLE 1

INTERNATIONAL ENVIRONMENTAL LAW PRINCIPLES MENTIONED BY THE DISSENTING JUDGES IN THE 1995 NUCLEAR TESTS CASE

/////////
/////////
JUDGES
/////////
PRINCIPLES
Weeramantry
Koroma
Palmer
Intertemporal
p. 339

p. 413 (without use of the term per se)
Inter-generational
p. 341

p. 419
Precautionary
p. 342
p. 379 (without use of the term per se)
p. 412
Environmental Impact Assessment
p. 344

p. 411
Illegality of dumping radioactive waste into the marine environment
p. 345
p. 378 (stated as a broad duty no to permit the escape of dangerous substances)
p. 410
Damage must not be caused to other nations
p. 346
p. 378
p. 410



SOURCE: The 1995 Case, supra note 2

(Chart prepared by the author)



As the above table indicates, a total of six environmental principles have been assessed by the dissenting judges. For the purpose of this paper, the principles have been re-grouped in three more general principles. This is no more than a theoretical arrangement which is made for academic reasons and for ease of discussion. The three principles are:

1)      The precautionary principle (including the concept of environmental impact assessment and the intertemporal principle) ;

2)      The principle of sustainable development (including the concept of intergenerational rights);

3)      The preventive principle (including the principle that damage must not be caused to other nations and the principle of the illegality of introducing radio-active waste into the marine environment).

PART 3

THE FRENCH NUCLEAR TESTS: AN APPRAISAL FROM POLITICS, DISARMAMENT AND ENVIRONMENT

Before starting in the analysis of the existence and validity of the principles of international environmental law discussed in the judgment of the Court, a general overview will be given of the reasons for France to make those tests. Likewise some remarks about the consequences of the tests will be presented.

REASONS FOR FRANCE TO RESUME THE NUCLEAR TESTS

Some of the reasons can be found in the following ideas:

1.      The strategic reason: the negotiations for the Comprehensive Test Ban Treaty (CTBT)

The negotiations of the CTBT cannot be understood without analyzing the works of the Conference of Disarmament based in Geneve and the negotiations about the Treaty of Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons (NPT).[26]

Following to a preparatory process of two and a half years, at May 12th 1995 one hundred and seventy five participant states adopted a “package deal” comprised of four decisions in the Conference on the Non-Proliferation Treaty Review and Extension Conference:

1)      Consolidation of the process of assessment of the NPT;

2)      Principles and objectives for the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons and Disarmament;

3)      Extension of the Non-Proliferation Treaty on Nuclear Weapons; and

4)      Resolution in relation to the Middle East.

With the adoption of this decision a major step forward was achieved in multilateral disarmament: the indefinite extension of the treaty of Non-Proliferation. In that regard and for the purposes of this paper we ae interested in the two following points:

a)      The already mentioned indefinite of the Non-Proliferation Treaty (Third decision adopted); and particularly in

b)      The termination in 1996 of the negotiations in the Conference of Disarmament in Geneve of a “treaty for the complete prohibition of nuclear tests of universal and international scope and with an adequate system of verification”, in other words to adopt the CTBT (second decision adopted)

Therefore, in terms of French politics and as it has been mentioned. France was, to certain extent, obliged – for the quick pace of the negotiations in Geneve and New York – to participate and to sign the CTBT and consequently it was necessary for this country to carry out the nuclear tests before the CTBT was signed by the other four members of the “nuclear club”.[27] In consequence, the rapid progress towards a global tests-ban regime explains some of the reasons of the timing and the necessity of the French nuclear tests.

2.      The technological reasons

Harald Muller has indicated that the French tests are justified for three technological reasons:

“-   terminer la qualification de l’ogive TN-75; celle-ci est destine au missile stratégique M-5 SLBM, colonne vertébrale de la Force de frappe au cours du siecle prochain;

-          Obtenir des renseignements sur la sécurité et fiabilité des armes viellisantes de l’arsenal, dans la perspective de pouvoir les réparer sans problemas le jour ou les tests seront interdit;

-          Obtener des informations pour la simulation sur ordinateur.[28]

As it can be seen, France had the necessity to carry out the tests taking into consideration the necessity to maintain the security and reliability of its nuclear arsenal.

3.      The French politics of “raison d’etat”

France had probably as a main political motive the widh to maintain its national security and interest protected; to keep the principle of “raison d’etat” at its best. In this regard, Chirac is a follower of the politics of the Gaulle for whom nuclear power and the nuclear role of France was of utmost importance.

In an interview on remembrance of the 25 years of the death of de Gaulle in “L’Express” in 1995, the French intellectual Alain Peyrefitte refereeing to Chirac and the nuclear tests pointed out:

“qu’aurait fait de Gaulle a propos des essays atomiques? Premierement, il n’aurait pas hésité un instant a reprendre les essays, si son prédécesseur les avait interrompus. Deuximement, il aurait sans doute gardé le secret, au moins jusqu’au premier essai, peut-etre meme apres. Troisiemement, il aurait alor poussé ses ministres a attaquer fort, a montrer que ce qui etait non pas de reprendre les essays, mais de les avoir interrompus! Mais cétait non pas de reprendre les essais, mais de les avoir interrompus! Mais cétait de Gaulle.[29]

In defense of Chirac, it should be stressed that the World in which de Gaulle lived and governed France – at the end of the second world war and at the beginning of the “cold war” – was different from the present one[30] were the global order or “global disorder” has slightly moved the world scenario from Europe to the United States and keeping in mind that in the future that scenario may rest un China. In that regard, a vision of a bipolar world fifty years ahead (US together with Europe counterbalancing China) is a new framework to be thought.

Considering the later, the French nuclear test also can be interpreted as the search – from the government of the Hexagone – for a nuclear re-affirmation of the French republic. In that view, only France and the United Kingdom – as nuclear powers – will be the reliable players to maintain the security in Europe in the years ahead. These two nations could also counterbalance – and this is an audacious opinion – the economic growth of regional European powers like Germany.[31]



CONSEQUENCES OF THE RESUMPTION OF THE NUCLEAR TESTS



Some short long term consequences of the tests are the following:



1.      The Negotiations of Disarmament and the Political Situation of France

The CTBT has an uncertain future in the following years. The absence of India in the CTBT is a major shortcoming for the success of the treaty and particularly for its definitive entry into force since 44 ratifications (including the nuclear powers and the threshold states India, Pakistan and Israel) are necessary for the treaty to be legally binding. In relation to the provisions of the CTBT, each one of the 44 “nuclear states” has a period of three years to sign and ratify the treaty. After this period – if there are not enough ratifications – a Conference will be convened to assess the future of the CTBT. Thus if any of the 44 countries does not sign the treaty in the following three years the CTBT may will never entry into force.

India in defending its position for no t signing the CTBT indicated that the treaty was discriminatory because it allows the five nuclear powers to maintain its nuclear capacity while prohibit such capability to other countries. Nevertheless about the political reasons of India:

“on peut se demander si les héritiers de Nehru ont vraiment voulu defender la cause du disarmament nucléaire ou si, par cette manoevre, ils nónt pas plutot souhaite garder ouverte leur proper option nucléaire” [32]

Interesting to know is, in relation with other multilateral instrument of disarmament, that the Chemical Weapons Convention recently entered into force (29 April 1997) in The Hague, and that Ms Wadhwa from the Indian Embassy has indicated:

“India’s decision to ratify the Convention was an extension of its well reasoned policy which calls for the elimination of all weapons of mass destruction within a well defined timeframe and under international supervision. India considers the Chemical Weapons Convention it be a model disarmament Convention since it is non-discriminatory, which does not have special categories of countries and imposes equal rights and obligations on all countries”.[33]

For France to have conducted the nuclear tests in the Mururoa Atoll was a major step forward in terms of its nuclear policy and political prestige of world power. Likewise the tests definitely will help this country to maintain the state-of-the-art technology in its nuclear arsenals.

2.      The signature of the protocols of the South Pacific Nuclear Free Zone Treaty (SPNFZ).

After the French nuclear tests a new nuclear-free zone has been established: The South Pacific Nuclear Free Zone Treaty (Rarotonga Treaty). This area joins the other nuclear-free zones such as the Latin American and Caribbean one (Tlatelolco Treaty), the African, the South East Asian (although there are reservations of the nuclear powers) and Antarctica. However, it should be noticed that the majority of the treaties creating nuclear-free zones and in general all the treaties of disarmament use to have the denominated “escape clause” which allow countries not being completely obliged by the provisions of the treaties.

3.      The ecological consequences of the nuclear tests for the inhabitants of the South Pacific islands

After numerous nuclear tests in the South Pacific Islands the ecological consequences area clear. Damage to the natural environment –in the atmosphere, in the soil and the sea –and also to the people of the close Pacific Islands.

Now let’s go back to the legal analysis of the dissenting opinions in the 1995 Nuclear Tests Case.

PART 4.

THE PRINCIPLES OF INTERNATIONAL ENVIRONMENTAL LAW – EXISTENCE AND VALIDITY:

After the short overview in the foregoing parts of this paper, this article will now assess the existence and validity of environmental principles. It is clear that in the aforementioned cases the majority of the Court did not express any opinions which could affirm such an existence without doubt, because the Court dismissed the request of New Zealand and therefore there is no ratio with regard to environmental principles. Nevertheless, the opinions of the dissenting judges do enunciate and rely on such principles of international environmental law.

4.1 Precautionary Principle:

A great number of authors recognize that it is difficult to find a satisfactory definition of the precautionary principle. [34]Gundling has noted that the concept of this principle has an elusive character because it contains a variety of elements. It is also very difficult to state a clear definition of this principle because of its international relevance and its diverse denominations.[35] The principle has been called: “principle of the precautionary action”, “principle of the precautionary basis”.[36] Hey has registered that in the official documents and the relevant legal literature legal terms like “precautionary policy”, “precautionary action”, “precautionary principle”, “principle of precautionary action” and “precautionary measures” are used.[37]

Nevertheless, despite the terminological imprecision, it is possible to extract common ideas about this principle which give support to its existence and validity in international law. Probably the most important definition which has been given of the precautionary principle is to be found in article 15 of the Rio Declaration of 1992 that states that:

“In order to protect the environment, the precautionary approach shall be widely applied by states according to their capabilities. Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent environmental degradation”.[38]

Lothar Gundling explains further:

“Precautionary action is a more stringent form of preventive environmental policy. It is more than repair of damage or prevention of risks. Precautionary action requires reduction and prevention of environmental impacts irrespective of existence of risks”.[39]

As it can be seen the precautionary principle has the fundamental objective to protect the environment before a situation carrying risks can cause any damage. Its application involves the idea that the lack of scientific certainty about the damaging effect to the environment cannot be considered as an impediment to take measures which can reduce or prevent this possible damage. The precautionary principle can thus be considered as one of the most important principles of the evolving corpus of international environmental law.[40]

In relation to the law of the European Union, the precautionary principle has been enshrined in the Maastricht Treaty of 1992, where in article 130 R paragraph 2 it is indicated as one of the fundamental features of the environmental protection policy of the European Union.[41] The precautionary principle has been clearly accepted in the second International Conference for the Protection of the North-Sea (London 1987) and also in the Third Conference (The Hague 1990).[42]

The majority of the scholars recognize[43] that the prime example of the precautionary approach at a global level is the Vienna Convention for the Protection of the Ozone Layer 1985.[44] And the Protocol to it signed in Montreal.[45] This convention and the protocol to it were signed despite scientific uncertainty and in spite of the huge consequences for the chemical industry. The subsequent revisions have each brought forward phase-out deadlines and states efforts in this regard represent strong examples of state practice in support of the precautionary principle.

The dissenting judges in the 1995 Case each discuss the precautionary principle, lending weight to the argument that it exists and has validity in international environmental law.

Justice Weeramantry, in applying the inter-temporal concept, held that the Court must bring to bear the knowledge of 1995 upon the Request before it, rather than applying the knowledge of 1995 upon the Request before it, rather than applying the knowledge of 1974 which in his opinion would be an “exercise in unreality”[46] Justice Palmer also held that, because the harm is a continuing one, the applicable law must be determined at the time the Court is called to determine it.[47] That is, in 1995 with the knowledge we now have in regards to nuclear damage.

Justice Weeramantry notes that the EIA process is gathering strength and acceptance and that the Court therefore applies it. In support for this proposition, Weeramantry cites the UNEP 1987 Guidelines on EIA. He notes the responsibility the Court has “at the apex of international tribunals”[48] to respect the trust placed in it with regards to the Global Palmer goes so far as to say that it is a legal duty of states to first establish that a planned activity does not involve an unacceptable risk. In support for this principle Palmer cites the ILC Article 12 obligation to undertake assessments of risk and the Noumea Convention Article 16 specific obligation to conduct EIAs.[49]

It is their discussion of the precautionary principle itself which leads all dissenting judges to conclude that the tests should have been halted.

Weeramantry traces the history of the concept and lists examples of treaties applying it. He notes that, because France is a party to the Maastricht Treaty, this formulation is of particular relevance to the case before the Court. He argues that one could expect the principle applicable to Europe to also apply to European activity in “other global theatres”.[50]

Palmer concludes that the norm involved in the precautionary principle has developed rapidly and may now be a principle of customary law which requires application in this case.[51] Koroma likewise uses the precautionary principle to conclude on the facts that “the evidence, though not conclusive, is sufficient to show that a risk of radioactive contamination may be brought about” and that the Court should therefore have taken action on New Zealand’s application.

In summary it can be said that in the opinion of the dissenting judges there is a general consensus that the precautionary existence and validity as a principle.

4.2 Sustainable Development Principle:

The concept of sustainable development emerged in the last decade.[52] The most renowned and relevant document which contains a definition of this concept is the Brundtland Report of 1987.[53] This report was headed by the Norwegian stateswoman Gro Harlem Brundtland which defines sustainable development as: “development that meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs”.[54]

This definition clearly emphasizes the existence of international rights, a concept coming from the law of “trusts” where the present generation holds the earth on trust for future generations.[55] This concept was relied upon as early as 1893 in the Pacific Fur Seal Arbitration.[56] Many treaties in the last twenty years have referred to this concept in one way or another. For example: 1973 Convention on International Trade in Endangered Species, 1979 Bonn Convention, 1985 ASEAN Treaty and the 1992 Biodiversity and Climate Change Conventions.[57]

The Rio Declaration crystallizes in articles 3 and 4 the Intergenerational Rights principle. Article 3 reads as follows: “The right to development must be fulfilled so as to equitably meet developmental and environmental  needs of present and future generations” and article 4 states “In order to achieve sustainable development environmental protection shall constitute an integral part of the development process and cannot be considered in isolation from it”.

It is the Marine context which provides most legal support for the existence and validity of this principle. In the Icelandic Fisheries Case, the ICJ surveyed existing fisheries conventions and state practice and made pronouncements about the rights of coastal and other states with regard to fishing rights. In doing so it stated that neither group of states had absolute rights, rather than both have a “duty to have due regard to the rights of other states and the needs of conservation for the benefit of all”.[58] Further UNCLOS III also relies on this principle in relation to sustainable use of resources.[59]

However it is not only the marine context which provides international opinio iuris on the sustainable development principle. Article 3(4) of the 1992 Climate Change Convention refers to the principle as do many articles in the 1992 Biodiversity Convention.[60] Article 2 of the latter convention defines sustainable development as “the use of components of biodiversity in such a way and at a rate that does not lead to the long-term decline of biodiversity, thereby maintaining its potential to meet the needs and aspirations of present and future generations”.

It is not clear exactly how this concept, if accepted as customary law, would be applied. Certainly there is the possibility that it could be used to support the legal standing of present generations to bring a claim in a similar way to co-trustees in traditional trust law.

Weeramantry explains the submission of New Zealand that nuclear damage by its very nature is lasting and the effects of it may be felt by many generations into the future. He finds that, because the Court is charged with administering international law, that it should take this emerging principle into account when it so clearly applies.

Palmer uses the principle as a further reason why the Court should have heard the case. That is, because the technology has given humankind the ability to massively alter natural environment, these consequences need to be examined lest we “imperil those who after us”.[61]

It is disappointing that the majority of the Court did not take advantage of the preeminent opportunity it had, in this context of potential nuclear damage, to make a comment about the principles of sustainability and intergenerational rights. However, what is certain, given the vast body of treaties refereeing to such rights and the comments by the dissenting judges, is that the principle has existence and validity which cannot be denied.

4.3  The Preventive Principle

The preventive principle may be said to be an overarching principle which includes the good neighborliness principle, the principle that damage must not be caused to other states or areas beyond national jurisdiction and the specific principle of illegality of dumping radioactive waste into the marine environment. It goes further than all of these however, as it requires action at an early stage, but not as early as the previously discussed precautionary principle.

The principle has been described by Sands:

“If a state  knows or has a reason to believe that an activity will cause, or is casing, damage to the environment in violation of the standards established under the rules of international law, it is under and obligation to prevent the activity from taking place.”[62]

It has customary law origins form the Trail Smelter case[63], later endorsed in the Corfu Channel case[64]. The Court held that states do not have the right to use their own territory in such a manner as to cause injury to other states or areas beyond their national jurisdiction.

The latin term being “sic utere tuo ut non laedas alienum”. The case of the Gabcikovo-Nagymaros Project, which was presented to the ICJ in March and April this year, also raises this principle and it will be most interesting to observe whether the Court makes any comment in the principle.

The renowned Principle 21 Stockholm Declaration, also repeated as Principle 2 Rio Declaration, encapsulates the duty of states not to cause harm to other states or areas beyond state jurisdiction. The UN general Assembly has referred to the principle as reflecting customary international law.[65] It may be said to be the modern day expression of the Trail Smelter principle and the foundation of the preventive principle. Sands refers to this principle as the “cornerstone of international environmental law”.[66]

The preventive principle has been further supported in many treaties ranging from the 1972 Stockholm Declaration, 1982 World Charter for Nature, to the 1992 Rio Declaration, Climate Change and Biodiversity Conventions.[67]

It is no longer disputed that Principle 21 represents customary law. What remains unclear, however, is exactly the extent of environmental damage which is illegal and is to be prevented. The preventive principle goes further that Principle 21, as it would appear to require states to prevent “environmental damage” within a state’s own territory. The extent to which this further requirements is valid and accepted is debatable.

While the preventive principle wasn’t named per se in the dissenting opinions of the 1995 Case, the concepts behind it were endorsed.

Justice Palmer sets out the New Zealand argument based on these principles that France was bound because it was party to the 1986 Convention for the Protection of Natural Resources and Environment in the South Pacific (Noumea). Further, Palmer lists all the treaties relied upon in order to support the existence and validity of the principles. There were seven significant treaties named.[68]

Justice Koroma supports his conclusion that preventive principles and duties exist by citing treaties such as the Moscow Treaty of 1963, the 1967 Treaty on Principles Governing the activities of States in the Exploration and Use of Outer Space, including the Moon and Other Celestial Bodies and the 1971 Treaty on the Prohibition of the Emplacement of Nuclear Weapons and Other Weapons of Mass Destruction on the Seabed and the Ocean Floor ad in the Subsoil thereof. These treaties have their object as the prevention of radioactive contamination of the environments to which they relate. He further cites the United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea, Part XII which pertains to protection of the Marine Environment. In light of such treaties, Koroma concludes that nuclear testing is not only prohibited, but that any damage caused is illegal.

Justice Weeramantry outlines the specific application of the principle of illegality of introducing radioactive waste into a marine environment. He cites chapter 22 of the adopted Rio Conference document, Agenda 21, as support for such principles specifically noting France’s President Mitterrand’s strong condemnation at that time of marine pollution. Weeramantry considers this as “self evident”[69] authority of the principle. He further refers to the principle not to cause damage to other nations as a “deeply entrenched principle, grounded in common sense, case law, international conventions and customary international law”.[70] In light of this he concludes that the Court must reach a determination as to whether a prima fascie case of danger to its rights has been made out by New Zealand.

PART 5.

PRINCIPLES OF INTERNATIONAL ENVIRONMENTAL LAW-OBLIGATIONS OR ASPIRATIONS?

Consideration of the existence and consequent status of principles requires Article 38(1) of the Statue of the International Court of Justice to be taken into account. This Article is generally regarded as a complete statement of the sources of international environmental law[71] by many scholars. It contains a list of five sources of international law, the third of which is important for the purposes of this paper:

1)      International conventions:

2)      International custom

3)      General principles of law:

4)      Judicial decisions: and finally

5)      The teaching of the most highly qualified publicists

The concept of “General Principles of law” has widely been accepted as allowing the International Court of Justice “to consider and apply general principles of municipal law”[72]. When the Court takes rules from municipal systems, those rules are not taken as they applicable in their own municipal systems; rather the Court edits, recreates or elaborates those rules. Therefore the rule applied by the Court is a mutated rule which emerged from municipal law, but which has been adapted and is now only applicable in the international law.

Some examples of general principles which have been applied by the ICJ include “principle of consent, reciprocity, and equality of states, finality of awards and settlements, and the legal validity of agreements, good faith, domestic jurisdiction, and the freedom of the seas”.[73]

The questions which remains open is to assess whether or not the group of principles of international law discussed above have validity and status in international law. Classical interpretations have indicated that there is no separate body of International Environmental Law (hereinafter “IEL”) and consequently that there are no particular principles of IEL.[74]

However, in the author’s view, the increasing global concern relating to the protection of the environment in the last 25 years, which has resulted in a vast body of laws and treaties being created, has changed the classical legal approach to this subject.[75] In the opinion of the author, it is possible to find and define principles which can only be related to environmental matters and that the preceding analysis of the 1995 Nuclear Tests Case highlights this existence and validity of such principles.

Birnie and Boyle have suggested that examples of these environmental principles possibly are “the precautionary action, sustainable development, equitable utilization of shared resources, etc.”[76] Other authors have expressed a broader view. Sands, for example, considers that there exist more principles directly linked to IEL. In his opinion there are seven principles of IEL:

“These are:

(a)    The obligation reflected in Principle 21 of the Stockholm Declaration and Principle 2 of the Rio Declaration, namely that states have sovereignty over their natural resources and the responsibility no to cause environmental damage:

(b)   The principle of preventive action;

(c)    The principle of good neighborliness and international co-operation

(d)   The principle of sustainable development

(e)    The precautionary principle

(f)    The polluter-pays principle; and

(g)   The principle of common but differentiated responsibility”.[77]

While these principles are receiving more attention in the international arena and their existence and validity can no longer be doubted so readily, it remains disputable whether these principles are binding or merely guidelines for policy action.

Now, this paper will be focus in the principles analyzed and its status in general IEL.

Sustainable Development:

Sands observes the several applications or aspects of the principle, namely consideration of future generations, equitable allocation of resources and environment and development integrations.[78] Handl observes that “without authoritative third party decision-making, conflicting claims about the concepts specific normative implications will abound and disputes over application will be exceedingly difficult to resolve”.[79]

It may be said, therefore that while sustainable development is a well-known concept, it’s binding nature is difficult to specify.

The precautionary Principle:

After an analysis of the precautionary principle, Birnie and Boyle conclude that:

“Difficult questions concerning the point at which it becomes applicable to any given activity remain unanswered and seriously undermine its normative character and practical utility, although support for it does indicate a policy of greater prudence on the part of those states willing to accept it”.[80]

More optimistically, also in relation to the precautionary principle, Sands concludes that, at a minimum there is sufficient evidence of state practice to justify the conclusion that the principle, as elaborated in the Rio Declaration, Climate Change and Biodiversity Conventions, has now received universal support. He further concludes that this supports an argument that the principle is now customary law.[81] Justice Weeramantry endorses Sands, specifically in the context of discussing the precautionary principle, as support for his finding that there are principles of environmental law.[82]

Preventive Principle:

The many applications and levels of this principle may not be readily said as a whole to be binding IEL. However, some of the principles under this banner have doubted status as binding principles of IEL. Principle 21’s Stockholm Declaration and the Good Neighbor and Co-operation principles area examples of principles which are well accepted by the international community and have indisputable status as IEL.[83]

The pleadings of over forty states in the World Health Organization request presented to the UNGA for advice on the legality of the use of Nuclear Weapons[84] provides further support for this status. The request included the issue of the existence of international environmental principles. Egypt, Iran, Solomon Islands and Mexico said Principle 21 was a principle of customary international law and no state denied this status in response.

General Status in IEL:

In relation to the status of general IEL, Handl argues that “general acquiescence in expressions of international concern over local environmental management is one this; states’ acceptance of specific international normative standards and rules that might impose severe limits on natural resources policies locally, is quite another”.[85]

The pleadings of the seven states[86] involved in the 1995 Case, provide a useful insight into the opinio iuris of at least those states with regard to the principles raised in the preceding sections of this paper.

In her analysis Fitzmaurice considers that most writers agree that there now exists “in general international law real and binding obligations on states on the protection of the environment whose breach involves responsibility thru a wrongful act.”[87]

While Sands acknowledges that the principles are not always endorsed by state practice and that some of them are only emerging rules of law, he argues that it is undeniable that these principles are becoming more important daily in international law.[88] In this sense their status is also evolving from vague principles to applicable, binding rules.



6. CONCLUSIONS

The overwhelming support expressed by dissenting judges for the existence and validity of several very important environmental principles cannot be overlooked as a contribution to the evolving corpus of law in this area. The precautionary, sustainable development and preventive principles discussed by the judges and as found in wide ranging international agreements, have definite validity in international law which can no longer be denied.

While it would be simplistic and legally incorrect to state that the 1995 Nuclear Tests case has itself created legally binding obligations of these principles, it is short sighted no to note the contributions it has made to increase the validity and status of principles of international environmental law.

It must note that the presentation of arguments relying on these principles to the world’s highest tribunal is in itself a major step forward. While the choice of the majority not to discuss or apply the principles is one which is regrettable for proponents of the environmental law development cause, it is hopefully not one which will be made again when the opportunity arises. Indeed, the Author await the current consideration by the ICJ of the Hungary and Slovakia dispute over the Gabcikovo-Nagymaros dam with interest, as similar principles of international environmental law have been raised.



[1] Diplomat, LL.B in International Relations (Diplomatic Academy of Peru), LL.M. in the International Law (The University of Hull, U.K.), Maitrise en Politique International (Univesité Libre de Bruxelles). Doctor in Law (Ponthifical Catholic University of Peru).

The views expressed here are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect those of the Government of Peru
[2] Request for an Examination of the Situation in Accordance with Paragraph 63 of the Court’s Judgment of 20 december 1974 in the Nuclear Tests (New-Zealand v. France)Case I.C.J. Reports 1995, p. 288 (hereinafter “The 1995 Case”) See also: Nuclear Tests Case (New Zealand v. France), Judgment of 20 December 1974, I.C.J: Reports 1974, p. 457. (hereinafter “The 1974 Case”).
[3] On the evaluation of this subject read the comments by Gillepsie, A. The 1995 nuclear tests case, The ICJ fails to address the merits of an international environmental concern. In: The New Zealand Law Journal, May 1996, Perera, A. Rohan, French Nuclear Tests in the Pacific – New Zealands Request for “An Examination of the Situation” – A Retreat into Judicial Formalism by the International Court of Justice?. In: 7, Sri Lanka Journal of International Law, December 1995; Bothe, M., Challenging French Nuclear Tests: A Role for Legal Remedies?. In: RECIEL, Volume 5, Issue 3, 1996; NicoSchrijver, Nuclear Weapon Tests and the international law: the New Zealand and France case and beyond, In: Institute of Social Studies, State and Society Relations Paper Nr. 96-03, 6 February 1996 (on file with the author); Kwiatskowka, B., New Zealand v. France Nuclear Tests case: the dismissed case of lasting significance. In: 9, Georgetown International Environmental Law Review, Washington, in the press, Daniele, Luigi, “L’Ordonnance sur la demande d’examen de la situation dans l’affaire des essays nucléaires et le pouvoir de la Cour Internationale de Justice de régler sa propre procédure”. In Revue Générale de Droit International Public, Issue 3, 1996.
[4] THe 1974 Case, supra note 2, p. 457
[5] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 288
[6] The 1974 Case, supra note 2, p. 460
[7] “Nuclear Test case” (Australia and New Zealand v. France), in: United Nations, Summaries of Judgments, advisory opinions and orders of the International Court of Justice, 1948 – 1991, New York, 1992, pp. 87 ff.
[8] Statute of International Court of Justice; Text in Brownlie, Basic Document in International Law, 3rd edition, 1983, Oxford.
[9] See infra part 3.1, p. 9
[10] France declared in 1974 not to continue its atmospheric nuclear tests. This unilateral declaration was considered for several years as an example of an additional source of international law. However, when France reasumed its nuclear tests in 1995 the concept of an unilateral declaration as a source of international law became controversial. On the classical interpretation of unilateral declaration as an additional source of international law see: Shaw, M.N. International Law, third edition, Cambridge: Grotius Publications Limited, 1991, at page 98.
[11] Gormley, W.P. (1976) Human Rights and Enviromental: The need for International Co-operation Sijthoff International Publishing Co., Leyden, at p. 146
[12] A few weeks later, France announced that instead of eight nuclear tests it would conduct only six
[13] Nuclear Tests case, I.C.J. Reports 1974, p. 477
[14] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 291
[15] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 291-292
[16] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 306
[17] Ibid. The judicial terminology of the Court the opinion of the judges can take three forms: a) dissenting opinion that states the reason why a judge disagrees with the Court’s decision, b) separate opinion “is written by a judge who has voted in favor of the Court’s decision, but who finds himself in disagreement with all or some of the Court’s reasoning”, c) declaration “is a brief indication of concurrence or dissent”. See: International Court of Justice. The International Court of Justice, ICJ The Hague 1986, third edition, at p. 62
[18] 1995 Order; para 63
[19] 1995 Order; para 64
[20] 1995 Order; p. 312
[21] See supra note 3
[22] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 339
[23] Id.
[24] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 379
[25] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 406
[26] About this subject it is recommended to see chapter 13 “The nuclear non-proliferation regime after the NPT Review and Extension Conference” of the SIPRI Yearbook of 1996. SIPRI Yearbook 1996: Armaments, Disarmament and International Security (Oxford University Press, 1996)
[27] “Chaud partisans d’une interndicion des essais, ls Australiens ont alors pris les devans er présenté a New York un projet de resolution adoptant le CTBT. Initiative couronnée des success puisque le 10 septembre 1996, l’assemblée générale des Nations unies a approuvé, a une écrasante majorité, une resolution adoptant le Traité d’interdiction globale des esais nucléaires:158 voix favorable, don’t celles des cinq puisances nucléaires declares, 3 votes contre (Inde, Libye, Bhoutan) et 5 abstentions (Cuba, Liban, Ile Maurice, Syrie, Tanzaine)”. Schmitz, Marc, Introduction, p. 6 In: De Becker, Martine: Muller, HArald et Scpaer, Annette, Essais Nucléaires. Fin de PArtie. Editions Grip, Institu Européen de Recherche et d’information sur la Paix et la Sécurité, 1996, 100 p. Likewise and consequent with the latter France, toguether with the United States And United Kingdom ad signed before – on 25 March 1996 – the South Pacific Nuclear Free Zone Treaty (SPNFZ), widely known as the Treaty of Rarotonga of 1985
[28] Muller, Harald. “CTBT: son historie, les enjeux, les perspectives d’avenir”. Pp. 28-29. In: De Becker, MArtine: Muller, HArald et Schaper, Annette. Op. cit.
[29] L’Express, No 2312 Semaine du 26 Octobre au 1er November 1995, “L’ombre du Général”, p. III
[30] The world and challenges of the time of the Gaulle differs completely from the present one. About this see: Aron, Raymond. L’Age de Empires et l’Avenir de France, Paris Défense de la France, 1945
[31] J. Goldblat during the courses of the Hague Academy of International Law in the summer of 1995 suggested this idea.
[32] Schmitz, Marc Introduction, p. 7 In: De Becker, Martine: Muller, Harald et Schaper, Annette
[33] “NRC Handelsblad”, The Netherlands, 14 May 1997
[34] Gundling, Lothar.”The status in international law of the principle of precautionary action”. Pp. 23-30. In: Freestone, David and Ijlstra, Ton (ed). The North Sea: Perspectives on regional environmental cooperation (special issue of International Journal of Estuarine and Coastal Law), London, Dordrecht, Boston: Graham and Trotman, Martinus Nijhoff, 1990, p. 25
[35] Id.
[36] Stebbing, A.R.D. “Environmental capacity and the precautionary principle”. Pp. 287-295. In Marine: Pollution Bulletin. Volume 24, number 6, 1992, p. 289
[37] Hey, Ellen. “The precautionary concept in environmental policy and law, Institutionalizing caution”. Pp. 303-318. In: The Georgetown International Environmental Law Review. Volume 4, 1992.
[38] Report of the United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, Rio de Janeiro, 3-14 June 1992, Vol. Ann. I, p.6
[39] Gundling, Lothar. Op. cit. p. 26 The same opinions have been given by Hey and Handl. Hey, Ellen. “The precautionary approach. Implications of the revision of the Oslo and Paris Convention”. In: Marine Policy, july 1991, p. 245. Likewise, Handl, Gunther. Environmental Security and Global Change: The Challenge to International Law”. London, Dordrecht, Boston: Graham and Trotman, Volume 1, 1990, p. 22.
[40] Freestone has indicated that: “The crux of the precautionary principle, action to prevent serious or irreversible damage should not be delayed until the scientific evidence is clear – by which time it might be too late”. Freestone David. “The road from Rio. International Environmental Law after the Earth Summit”. Hull: The University of Hull Press, 1993. p. 23
[41] Likewise, the same article recognizes that another fundamental principle which is part of the environmental policy of the European Union is the “Polluter Pays Principle”. In reference to the Precautionary Principle article 130 R paragraph 2 indicates: “Community policy on the environment shall aim at a high level of protection taking into account the divertisty of situations in the various regions of the Community. It shall be based on the Precautionary Principle and on the principles that preventive actions should be taken, that environmental damage should as a priority be retified at source and that the polluter should pay. Environmental protection requirements must ne integrated into the definition and implementation of other Community policies”. See: Treaty on European Union” (Maastricht, Netherlands, 1992). In: Foster, Nigel G. EEC Legislation. Third Edition. London: Blackstone Press Limited, 1992.
[42] Freestone, David, op. cit., p. 22 and following. See also: Cameron, Lames and Abouchar, Juli. “The Precautionary Principle: a Fundamental Principle of Law and Policy for the Protection of the Global Environment”, op. cit., pp. 4-5
[43] See for example: Benedick, R.E. (1991) Ozone Diplomacy, Harvard University Press, p.1
[44] Convention for the Protection of the Ozone Layer (Vienna) UKTS 1 (1990), Cm 910: 26 ILM (1987), 1529. In force 22 September 1988
[45] Protocol on substances which Deplete the ozone layer (Montreal) UKTS 19 (1990), Cm 977: 26 ILM (1987), 1550. In force 1 January 1989. Ammended 1990 OJED, No C11 (1991) p. 21
[46] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 340
[47] Ibid. p. 413
[48] Ibid. p. 345
[49] Ibid. p. 411
[50] Ibid. p. 344
[51] Ibid. p. 412
[52] The term “sustainable development” was introduced in 1980 by the International Union for the Conservation of Nature and Natural resources (IUCN) as “a new paradigm for future development strategies that aim to integrate economic, ecological and social objectives”. Mathias Buck, Research Associate, Ecological Centre for International and European Environmental Research
[53] World Commission on Environment and Development 1987 “Our Common Future”. Brundtland Report.
[54] Id.
[55] Brown-Weiss, E. (1990) Our Right and Obligations to Future Gnerations for the Environment, 84 AJIL (1990) 198, 199.
[56] Bering Sea Fur Seals Fisheries Arbitration (Great Britain v United States), Moore’s International Arbitrations, 755 (1893)

[57] See also:
1972 World Heritage Convention – Article 4
1977 ENMOD Convention – preamble
1985 Nairobi Protocol – Article 16(1)
[58] Icelandic Fisheries Cases (UK v Iceland), para 72, p. 31 and (FRGv Iceland), para 64, p 200
[59] See article 61(3)
[60] See Articles 1, 8, 11, 12, 16, 17 & 18
[61] The 1995 Case, supra note 2 at p. 419
[62] Sands, P. (1995) Principles of International Environmental Law. Vol. 1 Frameworks, Standards & implementation, Manchester University Press, Manchester & New York, 1995 p. 195
[63] Trail Smelter Arbitration, 33 AJIL, (1939), 182
[64] Corfu Channel Case, ICJ Reports (1949), 1.
[65] UNGA Res. 2996 (XXVII)(1972) asserts the Principles 21 and 22 of the Stockholm Declaration “lay down the basic rules governing the matter”. One hundred and twelve states voted for this resolution, none opposed, although it should be noted that the Eastern Block states did not attend the Conference and abstained on this Resolution, but have supported later treaties which recognize the normative character of the principle.
[66] Sands, supra note 54, p. 186
[67] See also:
1982 UNCLOS, Article 194 (1)
1985 ASEAN Convention, Article II
1987 Montreal Protocol, Preamble
MARPOL 73/78, Article I
[68] Namely:
1992 Agenda 21, Chapter 22, of the Rio Declaration
1958 Convention on the High Seas, Art. 25
1982 UNCLOS, Art. 194
1992 Biodiversity Convention, Arts. 3 & 14
1956 Statute of the IAEA, Art. 34
1992 Convention for the Protection of the Marine Environment of the North-East Atlantic, Art. 3(3)(a)&(b)
1972 London Dumping Convention

[69] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, at 346

[70] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, at 347
[71] Among these scholars Brownlie is notorious: See: Brownlie, I. (1990) Principles of Public International Law, 4th Edition, Oxford University Press, New York 1990, 9. 3
[72] Sands, supra note 54, p. 123
[73] Brownlie, supra note 63, p. 19
[74] Some legal scholars dislike the use of the term “international environmental law”, because they consider that there is no distinct “environmental” body of law with its own sources and methods of lawmaking deriving from principles peculiar or exclusive to environmental concerns”. Birnie, P.W. and Boyle, A.E. (1992)International Law and the Environment. Oxford University Press, 1992, p. 1.
[75] It is generally accepted that the global concern for the protection of the environment started at the first UN Conference on Human Environment in Stockholm in 1972
[76] Birnie and Boyle, p. 22
[77] Sands, supra note 54, at p. 183
[78] Sands, supra note 54, p. 208
[79] Handl, 1 YIEL (1990)
[80] Birnie and Boyle, supra note 66, p. 68
[81] Sands supra note 54, p. 462
[82] The 1995 Case, supra note 2, p. 342
[83] Supra note 75 and Sands, supra note 54 at 197
[84] See Sands, P. Reports from International Court of Justice in Year in Review, Y. Int’l Env. L,4 (1994)487-8
[85] Handl, G. (1992) “Environmental Security and Global Change: The Challenge to International Law” In: Lang, W. et. Al. (eds) Environmental Protection and International Law (1991) Graham & Trotman, 59 at 86
[86] Australia, Samoa, Solomon Islands, Marshall Islands, Federated States of Micronesia and New Zealand
[87] Fitzmaurice, M.A. (1995) “Responsibility for environmental damage as distinct from general state responsibility – the ILC Draft” in Netherlands Yearbook of International Law (1995) p. 202 at 210 quoting:  Mazzeschi, R.P. (1991) “Forms of International responsibility for Environmental Harm” in Francioni, F. & Scovazzi, T. (eds) International Responsibility for Environmental Harm (1991) p. 35
[88] Sands, supra note 54, p. 236

Comentarios

Entradas populares de este blog

EN HOMENAJE A LUIS MARCHAND STENS